Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
PHAINOMENON, 33 (2022): 25-50 Jairo José da Silva Universidade Estadual Paulista dasilvajairo1@gmail.com Reception date: 10-2015 Acceptance date: 09-2017 Abstract: I here present and discuss Husserl’s clarification of the genesis of modern empirical science, particularly its mathematical methods, as presented in his last work, The Crisis of Euro- pean Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Although Husserl’s analyses have as their goal to redirect science to the lifeworld and to reposition man and his immediate experiences at the foundation of the scientific project so as to overcome the “crisis” of science, I approach them from a different perspective. The problem that interests me here is the applicability of mathemat- ics in empirical science, to assess Husserl’s treatment of this issue in order to see if it can be sustained from a strictly scientific point of view regardless of philosophical adequacy. My con- clusion is that it cannot. What Husserl takes as the “crisis” of science is inherent to the best sci- entific methodology. Keywords: Mathematized science, Husserl, Lebenswelt, The crisis of science, The applicability of mathematics. The lifeworld is not free of science, for science, after all, is part of life. Experi- mentation and testing of scientific hypotheses and theories, for example, to the extent that they ultimately rest on sensorial perception, either naked or instrumentally enhanced, are not essentially different from the prosaic activities of the lifeworld, such as feeling the texture of a fabric or checking a piece of information. Yet, although perception pertains to the lifeworld, the scientific interpretation of perception does not. Experimental data, which are never mathematically precise (no one will ever read the value of, say, on a scale) are for scientific purposes often interpreted as approximations to the “real” values of the physical magnitudes being measured, which the theory tells us to expect (for ex- ample, ). ISSN: 0874-9493 (print) / ISSN-e: 2183-0142 (online) DOI: 10.2478/phainomenon-2022-0003 26 Jairo José da Silva All sorts of vicissitudes are thought to stand in the way of exactness, the deficien- cies of human attention, the inaccuracy of sensorial perception, unforeseeable local fluc- tuations of relevant parameters, in short, “errors” of all sorts. The experimental scientist, then, inhabits two different worlds, the lifeworld and the world of science; he perceives as a man of the lifeworld but interprets his perceptions with the idealized scientific picture of empirical reality firmly rooted in his mind. He is convinced that despite his efforts empirical reality will never disclose itself adequately to the senses; no matter how much his sensibility is enhanced by scientific instruments or how careful he carries out his measurements. Le tourbillon de la vie will always interfere. The lifeworld is the world of the “a peu près”, but exactness prevails in the puri- fied, pristine world of science. A cannonball follows a trajectory perfectly determined by a quadratic function, space is filled by an electromagnetic field precisely determined at each point, the metric of space-time is unambiguously given by some differential form, etc., etc. Behind the stage where life happens there lies, or so science presupposes, a hid- den structure of mathematical precision. But science is interested in the hidden structure, not the drama happening on stage. From the perspective of science, the reality accessible to the senses is a more or less deceptive manifestation of the true reality that will remain forever hidden to the senses. Thereby, as a matter of principle, not mere fact, the senses are necessarily impotent to reach real reality in an adequate and apodictic manner. Husserl saw a problem here. It is a basic tenet of empiricism, to which science pledges allegiance, that scientific theorizing must be confronted with experience and that in experience alone it can be validated. But scientific experimentation, no matter how refined, is basically and ultimately touching, seeing, smelling, tasting and hearing; the scientist must eventually use his eyes to check to which number in a numerical scale the pointer is indicating (or better, within which more or less fuzzy range of the scale the pointer is located). But if sensorial perception is a priori disqualified as a provider of adequate knowledge, is not science a priori undervaluing the validation it seeks? What is the point of empirical testing? Moreover, by alienating the world as man experiences it is science not ipso facto alienating man? Husserl answers both questions affirmatively. He concluded that modern science is, and has from its beginning been immersed in a “crisis” characterized by the alienation of man and all that makes sense to him. This “crisis”, as Husserl saw it, poses problems for philosophy and culture in general, including, as we will see, understanding the scientific project itself. Science and the Lebenswelt 27 I will be more explicit below; at this point, I only want to show what direction Husserl believed a way out of this critical situation (which is in fact a crisis of man) could be found. It is important to keep clear, however, that, for Husserl, the crisis of science is not a crisis internal to science. Scientific methodology is a scientific affair; philosophy has nothing scientifically relevant to say about it. Philosophy’s job is not “to fix” science but to understand it, disclose its true nature and clarify its methods (which include the mathematization that characterizes modern science since the times of Galileo) Phenom- enological clarification is, for Husserl, the first step in solving the crisis of science. To accomplish this, Husserl embarked on a journey in search of the origins of modern science. This meant first and foremost the investigation of the intentional genesis of the scientific conception of empirical reality, “unpacking” its many layers of sedi- mented meaning so its true nature can be brought to light. What is finally revealed is that empirical reality as conceived by science is not real reality, only an intentionally elabo- rated idealization of the sole true reality, that perceived through the senses, devised for methodological purposes. For Husserl, our modern mathematical science of nature deals with reality as perceived (the only true reality) by dealing with a symbolic-mathematical surrogate of it. Husserl also detected a tendency to “forget” that goes along with the bestowing and sedimentation of intentional meaning, which obliterates intentional constitution and takes as given what is only a product. Eventually, a reversal of ontological and epistemo- logical priorities takes place, the originally given empirical reality, that which is experi- enced with the senses, losing its status of true reality and being substituted as such by a mathematically purified surrogate. The world of science where the immediate sensorial perception of man is degraded as “rough” and “imperfect” becomes the real world. Thus science “naïvely” embraces Platonism as its “official” philosophy. Husserl believed that the right order of priority had to be reestablished if the crisis of science was to be solved; that the mathematical world of science must be “unmasked” as a product of intentional action devised for methodological purposes and the world experienced through the senses restored to the dignity of the true real world. This required, in particular, that the ideali- zations and presuppositions that go into the intentional constitution of the world of sci- ence be brought to light, a task carried out in full in the first sections of Crisis. This is also true in the philosophy of mathematics, whose task is to clarify not rectify. In connection with this it is instructive to mention what the 1952 Nobel Prize winner Felix Bloch (Bloch 1976) had to tell about a conversation he had with Werner Heisenberg, of whom he had been the first 28 Jairo José da Silva The world, however, is not only what we (or a generic I) have actually experi- enced, it also contains what can in principle be experienced. The horizon of possible ex- periences beyond experienced reality, however, or so Husserl thinks, is not a closed to- tality already completely determined in itself. This is a presupposition of science, not of the man of the world. But, and this is, I believe, very important, it is only by presupposing this that science can accomplish the task it imposed upon itself of anticipating experience beyond the possibilities of rough anticipation available in the lifeworld. One aspect of Husserl’s clarification interests me particularly. By revealing the true nature of empirical reality as conceived by science, Husserl made comprehensible the apparent “mystery” involving the applicability of mathematics in the empirical sci- ence. He has clearly shown how such a thing is possible (although not so much how it works), that the empirical science of nature can be mathematized because empirical real- ity as conceived by science is already mathematical. Not the actual reality experienced through the senses (not to the extent required by science anyway), but the scientific image of it, a mathematically improved version of our perceptual “first draft” of reality. Galileo told us that the book of nature is written in mathematical characters and cannot be under- stood by those who are not conversant with mathematics. This remains strictly true. What Husserl has shown is that this book is not a picture of nature, but a novel about nature. It tells a fictitious tale from which we can, nonetheless, infer important things about the world as experienced by us. This imposes upon the philosopher of science the task of investigating how and why this book was written and its narrative resources if he wants to understand why and how it can tell anything about the reality we experience through the senses and, more importantly, why it is so efficient at that. The transcendental history of empirical science is the history of its intentional constitution. This is a job for phenomenology (to which the initial part of Crisis, essen- tially chapter II, particularly §9, is dedicated), but cannot be done without the assistance doctorate student: “We were on a walk and somehow began to talk about space. I had just read Weyl's book Space, Time and Matter, and under its influence was proud to declare that space was simply the field of linear operations. “Nonsense,” said Heisenberg, “space is blue and birds fly through it.” This may sound naive, but I knew him well enough by that time to fully understand the rebuke. What he meant was that it was dangerous for a physicist to describe Nature in terms of idealized abstractions too far removed from the evidence of actual observation. In fact, it was just by avoiding this danger in the previous description of atomic phenomena that he was able to arrive at his great creation of quantum mechanics.” Husserl would certainly take side with Heisenberg. But it is by presupposing this that science can make unrestricted use of classical logic, the principle of bivalence (or excluded middle) in particular (see da Silva, 2013). Science and the Lebenswelt 29 of factual history (which, however, Husserl barely touches upon). Science has to do with sense-formations which have a (transcendental) history that requires phenomenological clarification. As I have already mentioned, Husserl’s strategy for clarifying the sense- formation “empirical nature” consisted in working his way back through layers of sedi- mented sense, “desedimenting” them so as to bring to light the intentional action that went into its constitution, eventually revealing the source from where sense originally emanated. At the end of the journey, Husserl finds the lifeworld, which, reversing scien- tific ontological priorities, he reestablishes as the original reality and the primary source of meaning. Thus, he thinks, the epistemological dignity of experience is reinstalled and coherence in the empiricist allegiances of science restored. The crisis of science, Husserl believed, was not confined to science; it spread to philosophy and psychology, blocking the way to a truly philosophical universal science whose foundations, Husserl insisted, must be firmly rooted in the lifeworld. Descartes, the philosopher who took mathematical extension as the essence of the physical body, borrowed from mathematics the criterion of truth, advocated a mathematical methodol- ogy for reasoning, and, more importantly, conceived the idea of a mathematical scientia universalis, is a perfect example of the new philosophical Zeitgeist that “contaminated” modern philosophy. Descartes’ philosophy and that of those who followed him, Husserl claimed, would be impossible without Galileo’s conception of reality as a closed mathe- matical manifold, a “rational unified system” (Husserl, 1970: §11). To overcome the crit- ical alienation situation in which science, philosophy, and man are immersed, Husserl proposed a return to the lifeworld, the source where sense originally flows. But, again, the search for the origins of modern science, the careful investigation of the intentional constitution of scientific sense-formations, the clarification of scientific methods, and the re-establishment of the ontological and epistemological dignity of the lifeworld is not to be carried out against science, for nothing is wrong with it or its meth- odological strategies. Nonetheless, if the ties of science with the lifeworld are not re- paired, Husserl believed, science risks being incomprehensible, even absurd. Only by The transcendental history of modern physics is intertwined with that of mathematics, which plays such a pivotal role in it. Modern physics, with its characteristic sense, could not have been constituted inde- pendently of the shift of sense that accompanied the creation of Greek geometry. An investigation of the intentional genesis of geometry and its objects was carried out by Husserl in his essay “The Origins of Geometry”, which appears as an appendix in W. Biemel’s edition of Crisis. Jacob Klein (Klein, 1992) has argued that the task would not be complete without a similar investigation concerning the concept of num- ber (about this see Hopkins, 2011). 30 Jairo José da Silva reestablishing “de jure” ontological and epistemological priorities, he thought, could sci- ence make sense, its methods and fundamental hypotheses clarified and circumscribed, and its criteria of validation firmly secured. So, although the development of a fully ar- ticulated philosophy of science was not its primary goal, Crisis contains the most articu- late reflection on scientific issues on Husserl’s part (at least as far as the physical sciences are concerned). I here want to examine it more attentively, to verify the extent to which it enlightens us about the nature of science and its methods, but also its shortcomings, the extent to which Husserl’s struggle to safeguard man from alienation can jeopardize the effectiveness of science and the accomplishment of its task. Crisis begins with a detailed historical account of the genesis of modern (seven- teenth century) physical science, whose characteristic trait is mathematization. For Hus- serl, the spirit of the new science was born in ancient Greece, where eastern geometry, essentially a technology pertaining to the lifeworld, was completely redefined as the sci- ence of an idealized rational domain of becoming (geometric constructions). Galileo pro- moted the same radical shift of sense concerning empirical reality, pushing it a little fur- ther. Besides conceiving empirical reality as an ideal, mathematized domain of being (not becoming) he also posited it as existing and completely determined in itself. Thus, Husserl thought, the germ of a crisis was instilled in science. The consequences were many, the downgrading of perception as the privileged means of access to empirical reality, the opening of doors to symbolization and symbolic manipulations, sometimes carried out in complete disregard for what the symbols meant (which Husserl called “technization”), the refusal to grant objective status to certain perceptual aspects of things (colors, for example, are no longer seen as objective properties of bodies, but subjective impressions caused by light of determinate frequency reflecting on the body’s surface and falling on our retinas, with no objective reality), in short, the alienation of man from his living ex- perience and all that makes sense to him. A very important aspect of modern science, as Husserl clearly saw, is the mathe- matization that characterizes it. Concerning this, two questions immediately impose themselves: 1) How is it possible that mathematics has anything to say about empirical reality? 2) How is it possible that mathematics is scientifically so effective? We can easily extract from Husserl’s considerations a correct answer to (1), but, unfortunately, he does not have anything to say about (2). More than anything, Husserl worried about the intro- mission of mathematics, particularly purely symbolic mathematics, in empirical science, for it could lead to alienation. His goal was to place man in control again, not investigate Science and the Lebenswelt 31 the scientific usefulness of mathematics (although his recipe for avoiding man’s aliena- tion also serves the purpose of making it impossible for technization to lead scientific methodology astray – at a price though, for the “blind” use of meaningless symbols has an important heuristic role in science). If the sense sedimented in routine scientific prac- tices, concepts and methods could be, at least in principle, reactivated, he thought, man would once more be in charge, and shifts of sense, particularly those that symbolization could induce, would be avoided. Husserl also wanted to regain the lifeworld for science, which, of course, could not be a mathematical science. He stood against mathematization being seen as the dis- tinctive trait of scientificity. This went along with a somewhat critical disposition con- cerning the role of mathematics even in empirical science. Since the lifeworld is the real world and the world of science a construct devised for methodological purposes, mathe- matical methods must be carefully circumscribed so as to prevent science from alienating itself from reality. The important question, however, is whether this is, from a strictly scientific perspective, desirable. I believe that it is not, that Husserl’s re-installment of the lifeworld as the sole source of meaning in science translates into the requirement that each scientific proposition must individually express the idealization of a possible expe- rience. This requirement does not correspond to the methodological practices of science and would, if enforced, seriously jeopardize their effectiveness. Science must alienate the living reality of man so as to accomplish its task. I will come back to this later; for now, let us spend some time with Husserl. For him, as I have already noted, although the crisis of science was intensified by the creation of the modern mathematical science of nature from the seventeenth century on, its origins can be traced back to the ancient Greeks. However, Husserl claimed, de- spite the idealization and systematization (i.e. axiomatization) that geometry knew in the To make clear what I have in mind, let me give an example. The complex-valued wave function of quan- tum mechanics does not correspond to a real wave or, directly, to anything in the world. According to the standard Copenhagen interpretation, only the square of the modulus of the wave function has some physical meaning, namely, a probability density, which, by the way, is hardly a purely physical entity. In a sense, the wave function “codifies” in mathematical form all the relevant information about a physical system, information we can “extract” whenever we want. As the great mathematician and physicist (and part time philosopher) Hermann Weyl claimed, physical theories, together with their heavy mathematical apparatus, are symbolic constructions that touch reality only at few points, but that must, then, “check”. If they do not, the entire theory, together with its mathematics (and maybe even its underlying logic), must be reexamined and fixed. The relations of science with reality are more subtle and, we could say, more superficial than Husserl believed necessary to rescue man from the situation of alienation vis-à-vis the world that science impinged on him. 32 Jairo José da Silva hands of the Greeks (from Tales to Euclid), they never believed that the geometrical do- main was a closed one completely determined in itself where facts subsisted sub specie aeternitatis, waiting only to be revealed; a domain in which “everything that ideally ‘ex- ists’ in the geometrical space is from the start already univocally decided in all its deter- minations. Our apodictic thinking only ‘discovers’, in its infinite progression, stepwise, according to concepts, principles, reasoning and proofs, what from the start, in itself, truly already is” (Husserl, 1970: §9). For Greek geometers, geometry had to do with ideal pos- sibilities of constructions, with becoming, not being (despite Plato’s interpretation). Modern geometry, contrary to ancient geometry, however, conceives its domain as a “rational infinite domain of being systematically mastered by a rational science” (Husserl, 1970: §8), “an infinite world, closed in itself, of ideal objectivities presenting itself as a field of investigation” (Husserl, 1970: §9). How such a conception came about, the idealizations and presuppositions it harbors is the theme of Husserl’s essay The Ori- gins of Geometry, which sets a model for works in transcendental history. The distinctive trait of Galilean physics is the mathematization (rather, geometri- zation) of empirical reality, and its most basic presupposition is that empirical nature is a mathematical Universum in the geometrical sense, i.e. an infinite realm of mathematical idealities closed and completely determined in itself into which mathematics only has access (Galileo’s famous “the book of nature is written in geometrical characters...”). Nature is geometric, and only geometry has adequate access to the secrets of nature. In this Universum, moreover, all co-beings are submitted to the omnipresent legality of a universal causal regulation. To the question “how is it possible ‘to know the world phil- osophically’, that is, in a seriously scientific manner, [building] systematically, in some way a priori, the world, the infinity of its causalities, from a meager stock of what is possible to establish in direct and relative experience?” (Husserl, 1970: §9), mathematics seems to provide the answer. By conceiving empirical reality as a geometrical Universum, modern science treats nature like but not exactly like geometry treats the geometrical do- main. The difference, which Husserl is careful to point out, is that whereas geometry is able to reach for the legality subjacent in the geometric realm a priori and once and for Has the collapse of the “classical” conception of causality brought about by quantum mechanics changed this picture in some way? According to Husserl, it did not. In quantum mechanics, nature is still “mathe- matical in itself, given in formulas and interpretable only in formulas” (Husserl, 1970: §9). Moreover, cau- sality is not completely eliminated in quantum mechanics, since the “state” of a system at any given point in time still strictly depends on its state at any previous instant, the “state evolution” being mathematically regulated. Science and the Lebenswelt 33 all, science can only rely on the meager stock of experience and so can never touch the mathematical legality that supposedly lies within the core of empirical reality in a com- pletely satisfactory manner. Why is it so difficult to extract from nature its mathematical structure? Why can we not have access to it as we have to the structure of the geometrical realm? I will come back to this later, but I can already reveal what I think Husserl’s answer was: in fact, mathematics is not in nature (as we perceive nature), not at least to the extent that science presupposes; mathematics is only in our scientific dealings with nature. So, the mathematical structuring science imposes on our perception of nature must be determined in conformity with the data of perception (and as scientific imagination deems appropriate), not a priori and definitely not once and for all, since the field of perception has an open horizon. Husserl’s search for the sources of science, as I have previously mentioned, in- volves uncovering hidden presuppositions which, by remaining hidden, make it difficult, if not impossible, to correctly understand scientific methodology and draw its limits of jurisdiction. Let us consider one, related to the mathematization of secondary qualities, such as color, texture, etc. Modern science is well-known for “subjectifying” them, which can only be recovered objectively by indirect means. As such, secondary qualities belong to the realm of the subjective-relative that is of no concern for science but can be recov- ered as something else in the objective-absolute (that is, valid for all) realm of science. For example, the subjective sensation of color can, for scientific purposes, be replaced by the wavelength (or frequency) of the radiation that “produces” the color sensation. This, however, Husserl says, presupposes that “the specifically sensible qualities (the ‘content’) experienceable in the bodies given to intuition be intimately connected [one to another] according to a rule and, in a very particular way, to forms that belong to them according to their essence” (Husserl, 1970: §9). The mathematization of secondary qualities, then, requires that sensible, intuitive “contents” be related with strict legality not only to one another but also to mathematical forms, which can act as objective substitutes of them. But this, Husserl observes, does not go by itself. Despite the evidences the Pythagoreans have already brought to light, this is a presupposition, a hypothesis, justifiable only by Mathematical domains are subsumed to concepts, and it is by inquiring their sense that mathematics can theoretically master them a priori and once and for all. The concept of nature, on the other hand, cannot serve the same purpose; empirical science is then constrained to investigate its extension so as to master it theoretically. 34 Jairo José da Silva the Galilean belief in a Universum où tout se tient and whose internal connections can only be explicitly rendered mathematically. Once intuitable contents are replaced by mathematical entities (numbers and the like), the covariance of intuitable contents experienced in the lifeworld can, under the hypothesis of strict underlying legality, be mathematically expressed in formulae involv- ing only the mathematical representatives of experienceable contents. These formulae are then mathematical expressions of natural laws on whose basis intuitions can be antici- pated. Mathematics now controls the lifeworld. According to Husserl, “the indirect math- ematization of the world, which expresses itself as a methodic objectivation of the world of intuition, produces general numerical formulae which, once found, can serve in appli- cations to accomplish the objectification of singular cases subjected to them. The formu- lae express general causal connections, ‘laws of nature’, laws of real dependence, under the form of ‘functional’ dependence among numbers” (Husserl, 1970: §9). What sort of hypothesis is this, that nature is subjected to strict and mathematically expressible legality? Is the fact of science and its unquestionable success a confirmation of this “Galilean” hypothesis? According to Husserl, this is “a very surprising hypothesis indeed. Our empirical science, which has for centuries been its confirmation, is thus a confirmation of a very surprising nature. The surprising thing is that the hypothesis re- mains, despite its confirmation, always and ever a hypothesis. Its confirmation (the only conceivable for it) is an infinite succession of confirmations” (Husserl, 1970: §9). Gali- lean science, Husserl thought, is founded on a “hypothesis” that cannot be either con- firmed or disconfirmed, which makes it a rather peculiar hypothesis. This demands an explanation. Could it not be that the “hypotheses” that nature is a domain existing and com- pletely determined in itself submitted to strict legality, which mathematics can only ade- quately express, be given a “positivist” reading? Such as, for instance, the Copernican heliocentric “hypothesis”, which can be seen as a mathematical scheme “to save the phe- nomena” with no consequence for reality as it really is, a view the Church pressed on Galileo, but that Galileo refused? (According to historians of science, such as Koyré and Crombie, Galileo was definitely not a “positivist”; mathematics was not, for him, an in- strument for conveniently structuring the phenomena, but was built in the structure of nature itself). Could Husserl be ranged with the “positivists”? Was mathematization, for Husserl, only a way of structuring our experience of reality while reality itself remained inaccessible? Science and the Lebenswelt 35 Such an interpretation, I believe, is completely alien to Husserl’s thought. It would require a distinction between noumenal and phenomenal realities, with phenomenal real- ity, and it alone being given, for reasons of convenience, a mathematical structure. This mixture of Kantianism with pragmatism has no place in his philosophy. Husserl’s dis- tinction is not between phenomenal and noumenal realities, but between the lifeworld and what science takes for the real world. Our experience of reality, he thinks, is definitely not-mathematical or at least not mathematical in the same sense as scientific reality is and can only be mathematized in the molds of science by being idealized, that is, by being put out of reach of experience. The reality we experience through our senses, however, Hus- serl claims, is reality itself, the only real one. Mathematized reality, on the other hand, is only an idealization of reality, not in a metaphysically serious sense real. So, for him, there is no distinction between reality itself and experienced reality: what we experience is reality itself. Mathematized reality is neither reality itself nor experienced reality, only an ideal model of experienceable reality devised for methodological purposes. Although science depends on the presupposition that nature is submitted to laws, natural laws do not necessarily follow, at least not completely, from the concept of nature; they have to be read in the phenomena. In nature, however, the realm of the actually experienced is constantly open to the horizon of the still to be experienced. Unlike math- ematical domains which are in stricto sensu capable of being completely surveyed a pri- ori, those of science cannot. Empirical science, then, must always be ready to be shaken by what experience may bring; the legality reigning in nature must be constantly rede- signed and re-established. Hence, the foundational “hypothesis” of science cannot ever be definitively either confirmed or refuted. The conclusion then offers itself; this, in fact, is not an empirical hypothesis, but a transcendental one, a conditio sine qua non that predetermines the field of possible experiences, that is, reality; nature, so the “hypothesis” establishes, is subjected to strict legality. Nevertheless, there is more, the experimental scientist, who is in charge of testing scientific hypotheses, whose eyes, ears, hands, tongue, and nose have business solely with empirical reality, has his mind firmly set on the idealized construct science substitutes for the living reality. In short, he plays the same game that the theoretical scientist does; he In case you are not keeping score, we have already considered two transcendental hypotheses in the con- stitution of empirical reality: 1) it is a domain of being existing and completely determined in itself, 2) it is a domain subjected to strict legality, which can be mathematically expressed (and only thus can be ade- quately expressed). 36 Jairo José da Silva too orients himself by “ideal poles”; he too presupposes strict legality. Numerical magni- tudes and general formulae are always the main source of interest, theoretical or experi- mental. Scientific hypotheses, suggested by “experimentally verifiable facts”, are already formulae and ideal relations. So, the experimental physicist cannot challenge the idealized world vision of the theoretical physicist and the “hypotheses” at its core. “Hence, the science of nature is subjected to a mutation of sense and a covering of sense that has more than one level. The interplay between experimental and theoretical physics [...] has a horizon of sense that has suffered a mutation.” For Husserl, then, the “mathematizing objectivism [...] attributes to the world itself a mathematical rational essence” (Husserl, 1970: §24). “[T]he substitution by which the mathematical world of idealities, which is a substruction [...] is taken as the only real world, that which is truly perceivable, the world of real or possible experiences: in short, our daily lifeworld” (Husserl, 1970: §9). Husserl deplores that Galileo did not question “the original sense bestowing act, that which, as idealization, acts on a primitive soil of all theoretical and practical life – the soil of the immediately perceived world” that lies at the basis of his method. Yet, Husserl thought, it is the lifeworld that interests us; it is in this world that we live; it is this world that we want to know inductively from experience (“the certainty of being of all simple experience is already an induction”). But in this world “we do not meet geo- metric idealities, nor geometric space, nor mathematical time with all its forms” (Husserl, 1970: §9). What, then, is the purpose of science? Husserl has the answer; it is “to correct in an infinite progression, by ‘scientific’ anticipations, the rough anticipations that are orig- inally the only possible within the effectively (actual or possible) experienced in the life- world” (Husserl, 1970: §9). In other words, the point of science is to anticipate experience more effectively than it is possible in the lifeworld; its job is to set ideals that, although actually unattainable, can direct our efforts into improving experience. In fact, although Husserl does not go into this, the mathematical science of nature anticipates experience only by anticipating the mathematical form of experience, its material content depending either on meaning already attributed to mathematical symbols or, if previously assigned meaning cannot be sustained, new meanings, whose assignment, however, falls short of the competence of science, since it depends on the scientists’ sensibility or guessing abil- ities. In short, under the presupposition that nature obeys laws whose form admits math- ematical expression, formulae are devised to express “natural laws”, which are then used Science and the Lebenswelt 37 to predetermine the mathematical form of future experience. (I will come back to this soon) The historical accuracy of Husserl’s considerations can be put to test by compar- ing his conclusions to the ones of a science historian expert (Koyré, 1973: 83; the English version is mine): The way Galileo conceives a scientific method implies a predominance of reason over mere experience, the substitution of ideal (mathematical) models for empirically known reality, the primacy of theory over facts. It was only thus that the limitations of Aristote- lian empiricism could be surmounted and a truly experimental method could be elabo- rated, a method in which the mathematical theory determines the very structure of exper- imental investigation, or, in Galileo’s own words, a method that uses mathematical (geo- metrical) language to formulate its questions to nature and interpret nature’s answers, which, by substituting the rational universe of precision for the imprecise world empiri- cally known, incorporates measurement as the fundamental and most important experi- mental principle. Husserl’s conclusions concerning the main traits of modern science are all sum- marized in this quote, namely, the reification of a methodological construct, the mathe- matical substruction of empirical reality, the downgrading of the lifeworld (the imprecise world of empirical experience, of the morphological, not the geometric) as a source of knowledge, the theoretical, mathematical predetermination of experience. Even though Husserl was not involved with factual history, he certainly hit the nail on the head con- cerning the factual development of physics. I now want to consider the problem of the applicability of mathematics in natural science more carefully. This question was raised in Crisis, where Husserl offered the key to understanding how this is even possible. But Husserl was also suspicious of the intro- mission of symbolic mathematics in science. The primacy of the lifeworld and Man’s immediate perceptions entailed, for him, that symbolization and the manipulation of sym- bols can only be allowed in science in the following cases: 1) when symbols have deno- tations that somehow relate to entities of the lifeworld or else, if symbols are void of any trace of intuitiveness; 2) when (necessarily meaningless) symbolic manipulations are part of a methodological strategy, a practical but essentially unnecessary way of dealing with definite contentual theories (i.e. theories that have to do with Man’s perceptions and are 38 Jairo José da Silva syntactically complete so as to be capable of settling any question that has a meaning in their domain – Husserl obviously thought that definiteness was an attainable ideal). This way of avoiding the dangers of “technization”, however, has two major shortcomings. First, although definite theories can stand as ideals, they are not, due to Gödel’s theorem, to be expected in general, and, secondly, symbolic mathematics has a much wider range of applicability in science than Husserl allowed it to have. Is there a better way of dealing with this problem? I want to propose one that takes inspiration from Husserl’s analyses of the genesis of modern science in order to account for the possibility of applying math- ematics in science, but that refuses his conservatism as to the range and scope of this application. The scientific inadequacy of Husserl’s views on the mathematization of science follows from his belief that mathematical methods should be kept under strict surveillance so as to avoid what he saw as philosophical problems. For science, however, from a meth- odological perspective, such methods are the very opposite of a problem. Moving to ever higher levels of mathematical abstraction and indulging in purely symbolic reasoning grant the theorizing scientist access to ever more powerful mathematical tools of formal investigation that often yield empirically testable consequences (even though most of the assertions of the symbolic theories he sets in action, those that involve empty symbols, do not directly correspond to anything in principle perceivable and a fortiori testable). For Husserl, however, algebra and other forms of symbolic reasoning, although often harmless, when symbols stand for “real” entities, can become problematic when symbols stand instead for “imaginary” ones (“empty” symbols). According to him, “[t]he powerful elaboration of signs and the modes of algebraic thinking, a decisive moment that has in a certain sense been rich in future consequences but, in another, disturbing for our destiny” (Husserl, 1970: §9). Symbolic reasoning, no matter in which guise or form, involving meaningful or meaningless symbols is, as Husserl recognized, a powerful sci- entific method, but it has also, he claimed, “disturbing consequences for our destiny.” The situation becomes critical, he thought, when symbols do not correspond to possible intuitions, for assertions involving such symbols are meaningless since their content can- not be traced back to the lifeworld and Man’s perceptions. The use of meaningful sym- bolic mathematics is not, for Husserl, in itself, a very serious problem, for it can be epis- temologically justified but, like light drugs, it can lead to the abuse of heavier ones. In fact, Husserl claimed, it is a short ride from the invention of algebra and its use in science Science and the Lebenswelt 39 and geometry (Descartes, Fermat) to the creation of purely formal, intuitively empty mathematics and the complete “technization” (and alienation) it led to. The problem of the epistemological justification of the scientific use of symbolic mathematics is not raised in Crisis, but it had been approached in a different context, involving instead the mathematical applicability of this methodology (for example, in Husserl’s 1891 Philosophy of Arithmetic in connection with the symbolic technology of arithmetic). Husserl, I believe, did not see any reason for dealing with the problem afresh when it surfaced again in connection with the scientific applicability of mathematics, for the scientific use of symbolic mathematics is, as he showed in Crisis, fundamentally, a mathematical one. Nevertheless, even the use of meaningful symbols, those that correspond through a series of idealizations to contents of the lifeworld, despite its justifiability, also counts as symbolization and a form of technization, although a less alienating one. For instance, analytic geometry already implies, or so Husserl thought, a “debilitation” of the sense of geometry, for it is no longer space, but a mathematical “image” of space that commands our interest. Yet, this is not, by far, the only case of symbolization in science. Algebra gave origin to purely formal mathematical theories, which, as Husserl claimed, when con- sidered in themselves, are perfectly legitimate formal ontological theories, that is, theories of formal manifolds (among which the definite manifolds given by “complete systems of axioms” stand out), but when extending (contentual) mathematical theories, and in par- ticular the mathematical theories of nature, can lead to loss of meaning and “alienation”: “[T]he original thinking,” says Husserl, “which gives sense to this technique and its true results (even if it is the ‘formal truth’ proper to the mathesis universalis) is here [i.e. in purely formal mathematics JJS] put out of the circuit.” This passage from the “mathemat- ics of real domains to formal mathematics” is correct and necessary, but “can and must be a method understood and utilized with full consciousness.” That is, we must be careful that “dangerous shifts of meaning” do not occur, which is to say, that “the original dona- tion of sense of the method, from where it takes its sense as the realization of the knowledge of the world, be always at our disposal.” The question that bothered Husserl can be formulated thus: How can the use of symbolic mathematics in science be philosophically justified from the point of view of a 40 Jairo José da Silva philosophy that puts Man’s perceptual experiences as the ultimate ground of justifica- tion? Let us first consider the use of algebra in physical geometry, the mathematical theory of physical space. Physical geometry is a science based on geometric intuition, which is a refinement, or better, an exactification of perceptual intuition. According to its original sense, the validation of geometric propositions depends on geometric construc- tions in space in which geometric truth is displayed directly to the mind’s eye, often via a sequence of constructions based on axiomatically valid elementary constructions and elementary facts (there is here a constant interplay between sense perception and its ex- actification, geometric intuition). Now, in using algebra in geometry – analytic, as op- posed to synthetic geometry – Descartes and Fermat transferred the burden of validation to algebraic, i.e. symbolic manipulations, no longer intuitive constructions. Despite the shift of sense introduced by analytic methods in geometry, symbols still correspond to geometric entities (which correspond, as their exactification, to things that either are or can be given in perception); algebraic manipulations can still be “decoded” into geometric constructions (which can, themselves, be “decoded” in terms of practices of the life- world). Technization is still, so to speak, under control; the original sense of geometry can be recovered. Formal mathematics, where symbols do not correspond to anything intuitable however, or so Husserl thought, more than technization for practical purposes introduces something more disturbing, alienation: purely symbolic manipulations that have no ties with experienceable reality. How, then, can they be justified? Based on Husserl’s treatment of “imaginaries” in mathematics, as presented in the double lectures delivered in 1901 in Göttingen, we may guess what his answer would be: formal mathematics can only be justifiably used in science if it is a consistent extension of definite, i.e. logically complete “meaningful” theories whose domains are idealizations of Man’s immediate experiences. Unfortunately, this will not do given that such a re- quirement would cripple scientific methodology (see da Silva, 2013). Furthermore, there is an even more fundamental problem that Husserl did not ad- dress in Crisis, but that had already been dealt with in much earlier works: how is it after all possible to obtain knowledge of entities of a type, belonging, for instance, to the geo- metric or empirical domain, by manipulating symbols (for example, algebraic symbols) referring to entities of a different type (numbers, in the case of algebra)? Part of the answer My point here, in a nutshell, is that Husserl’s answer to this question is not a good answer to another question, namely: how can the use of symbolic mathematics in science be scientifically justified? Science and the Lebenswelt 41 is available in his Philosophy of Arithmetic, and here it is: If the system of entities we want to know is formally identical to the systems of entities our symbols denote, then whatever is true in one is also necessarily true in the other. Let me explain what Husserl had in mind. Let A be our domain of primary interest and B an isomorphic copy of it. It does not matter what the elements of B are, I only suppose that B is more easily accessible to direct experience than A (whatever type of intuitive experience the direct inspection of A and B requires, perceptual or any other). Whatever is true in B, provided it involves only relations and concepts for which there are isomorphic correspondents in A, is also, upon reinterpretation, truth in A. Truth is preserved under isomorphism. This is how Descartes’ analytic geometry works: points are given numerical representatives in such a way that geometric properties are repre- sented analytically, and geometric constructions are replaced by algebraic manipulations isomorphically. B may also be a purely formal domain, defined by a formal theory, for which truth only has a formal sense. The applicability of mathematics in empirical science is also a matter of formal relations between mathematical realms, requiring as prerequisite the mathematization of our perception of empirical reality. This is how it goes. By retaining from perceptual experience objective form instead of subjective material content, a “rough” formal struc- ture that is already proto-mathematical is obtained that can be idealized into a mathemat- ical structure proper. Thus, an ideal mathematical mold is imposed upon experience “ex- actifying” the “rough” structuring we can extract from it by abstracting from perceptual experience. From this point on the applicability of mathematics in science is only a par- ticular case of the applicability of mathematics in mathematics itself. If, for example, we can find a domain B isomorphic to domain A that idealizes experience mathematically, the theory of B, provided it is expressed conveniently, i.e., in the language of A, is also true in A. However, in general, the first level mathematization of experience, our A, is still mathematically too poor to have interesting isomorphic copies with well-developed theories and can profit from being mathematically enriched into a domain B (we can think of this as immerging A into B by a convenient monomorphism). If this embedding is short of being a full isomorphism, the language of the theory of B may have symbols that are “imaginary” from the perspective of A, that is, symbols that have no interpretation in A. In this case, for Husserl, or so I claim, the theory of B can only be utilized for dealing with A if the theory of A is a definite, i.e., a syntactically complete, theory. 42 Jairo José da Silva In short, by abstraction and idealization, we go from the lifeworld into the world of mathematics. If this mathematical substitute corresponds to the lifeworld in such a way that mathematical symbols correspond to contents of the lifeworld isomorphically - sim- ilarly to what happens in analytic geometry, in which numbers and numerical variables stand for geometric entities and variables over the geometric domain in such a way so as to preserve the latter’s structural form -, technization (i.e. the substitution of the intuitable by the symbolic) can be justified along the same lines algebra is justified vis-à-vis phys- ical geometry. But when mathematical symbols have no representational value in the life- world, i.e. when mathematics is purely symbolic, the ties with the lifeworld are severed. Scientific theories with “imaginary” symbols are no longer, strictly speaking, theories of an idealized version of experienceable reality, but of an imaginary extension of it, a sym- bolic reconstruction of perceptual reality, in the words of Hermann Weyl. How, then, can they be epistemologically justified in a way that takes experience into account? Given that Husserl’s answer, or what I take for it, is unacceptable, is there a better one? There is one that imposes itself, I think: theories which incorporate “imaginaries” can only be tested as wholes (scientific holism) by means of their meaningful (i.e. testa- ble) consequences; isolated propositions cannot in general be empirically verified. The theory of B is scientifically justified provided that any assertion which can be interpreted in A, but whose justification involves in some way the theory of B, is verifiably true in A. Of course, the effectiveness of the theory of B in dealing with A can never be definitively justified once and for all, because a consequence may be derived that is false in A. This, by the way, is how Weyl solved the epistemological problem posed by purely symbolic manipulations in science (see da Silva, 2014). As I see it, Husserl may have been aware of this possibility; the problem is that it does not offer comfort for the alienation of Man; rather, it embraces it. “Blind” symbolic manipulations do alienate Man, his lifeworld, his experiences, and the testimony of his senses. Yet, science cannot do otherwise if it is to remain efficient. Holism, on the other hand, does not turn its back to the lifeworld, as it too gives Man’s perceptions a funda- mental role in the justification of scientific theories, no matter how symbolically “con- taminated” they may be (more globally than locally, though, as Husserl seemed to prefer). One point in Husserl’s analyses of the mathematization of science that I want to stress is the following: mathematics is not intrinsic to experienceable reality, but imme- diate experience may suggest possible routes of efficient mathematization of perception. The conflict Husserl detected between pure and applied mathematics seems to indicate Science and the Lebenswelt 43 this much. Pure mathematics can be known a priori and apodictically whereas “the con- crete universal legality of nature,” despite also being mathematical, is only accessible a posteriori and inductively; on the one hand, the purely mathematical (deductive) relation between reason and consequence, on the other, (inductive) natural causality. For Husserl, “[A] feeling emerges, little by little, with a sensation of malaise, of the obscurity inherent to the relation between the mathematics of nature and the mathematics of the space-tem- poral form [...]” (Husserl, 1970: §9). Why, Husserl questioned, does the mathematics of the real not also offer itself in an apodictic intuition, allowing complete axiomatization and deduction to take intuition’s place as the official truth-providers, just as in pure math- ematics, but is always at the mercy of induction from the facts of experience? In other words, why does the mathematics of the real not give itself directly to intuition? The fact that it does not, but that it must again and again be extracted inductively from experience seems to indicate that, for Husserl, mathematics, to the amount science requires anyway, is not intrinsic to our experience of reality. Quite the opposite, mathematization is im- posed on experience on the basis of what experience meagerly suggests (although what experience suggests is to some extent already mathematical or proto-mathematical in con- sequence of the ego’s intentional action in molding the crude data of perception). Math- ematization is only a convenient a posteriori structuring of experience that takes notice of the facts of experience but is not extracted from experience. Mathematics, as utilized by science, is not a given of experience; rather, it comes from the outside as a methodo- logical device. That experience, nonetheless, already has some mathematical or proto-mathemat- ical structuring is something that comes out clearly in Husserl’s account of the constitu- tion of perceptual space (for, remember, experience is already an intentional construct). Perceptual space, although not strictly speaking geometrical, is proto-geometrical; it has some structure on the basis of which, by idealization, a geometric manifold (physical space) is constituted. Idealization, after all, is not creation ex nihilo; indeed, as a process of exactification it requires something that is not “exact” to begin with; in this case, per- ceptual space and its perceivable structure. But not even this structure is only a matter of perception. Perceptual space also betrays a constitution; it is not simply given but a prod- Even the mathematical structure of physical space is not completely given once and for all as the history of physics clearly indicates. We have moved from a Euclidean to a non-Euclidean structuring of space (better, space-time) in the course of the evolution of science. 44 Jairo José da Silva uct of intentional psycho-physical systems whose task is to “process” raw sensorial im- pressions. The constitution of perceptual space – a structured system of possible positions of bodies (points) and the relations among them, such as: point A is closer to point B than to point C, A is between B and C, etc. – is a joint contribution of the senses and built-in psycho-physical intentional systems. These relations are perceptually accessible and more qualitative than quantitative. For Husserl, however, perceptual space is real space. This can be easily generalized. Our ordinary, pre-scientific experience of empiri- cal reality has also, inevitably, some structure. The experience of the world is not a chaotic mess, but a structured system of perceptions. And, as we know, structures are the subject matter of mathematics. Any structuring is mathematical and structuring relations, such as order, proximity, contiguity, and gradation of different types, among others, are mathe- matical in nature and so prone to mathematical treatment. Therefore, the structure of ex- perience is an aspect of the experience itself. Science may and does enrich it, idealizing it, “polishing” it, so to speak, introducing new objects and relations in it, but it does not create it ex nihilo. Now we have some inkling as to why mathematization works as a method: it is a way of extracting information regarding the structure of experienceable reality through more refined mathematical methods. Nevertheless, it cannot, by itself, if no semantic content is instilled into the symbols, tell us anything about the material con- tent of experience (the whats instead of the hows). Husserl admitted this much, namely, that experienceable reality is to some extent already mathematical; he only denied that it is mathematical to the extent science presup- poses. The lifeworld is not, as I have already noted, mathematics-free and Husserl knew it. What Husserl may have failed to see, since he did not emphasize it, was, first, that the objectivation of experience demands that its material content be relinquished in favor of its formal content, for form can only be objectified through language – indeed, no lin- guistic rendering of experience, being as it is, out of need, invariant under isomorphisms (true in all isomorphic copies of any domain where they are true), can singularize material content. Secondly, since science is necessarily formal in the sense mentioned above, it can benefit from purely formal-symbolic mathematics devoid of any material content. For Husserl, the project of science requires that the subjective realm of content (colors, sounds, etc.) has correspondents in the objective realm of form (frequency of radiation, longitudinal waves of determinate frequency and amplitude, etc.). But this is not, as Hus- serl seems to believe, a presupposition of Galilean science only, but of any objective sci- ence. Science and the Lebenswelt 45 By admitting a proto-mathematical structure to experience, Husserl in a way “hu- manizes” Platonism. Instead of a strictly mathematical reality out of perceptual reach, a proto or quasi-mathematical reality within human reach which can, for methodological purposes, be represented by an idealized, often structurally enriched mathematical pseudo-reality. However – and this is important – the entire process has only to do with the form of empirical reality. As long as material contents – themselves, not their symbolic “representatives” – are brought into science, mathematical methods of investigation completely lose their relevance (Goethe’s theory of colors, to give an example, is refrac- tory to mathematical treatment). If Husserl had seen this he would, I believe, be less con- cerned with preserving the possibility of recovering perception from its formal aspects alone. Maybe then he would accept that scientific theories, no matter the amount of math- ematics that goes into them, are always considered in themselves, independently of ex- ternal donation of material meaning to symbols (i.e. by associating content of experience to symbols), purely formal, and that this is why they can be so efficiently extended by purely formal means. There is no other way for the contour conditions imposed by per- ception to be taken into account, but by submitting theories to test as wholes by means of the formal consequences we extract from them and into which we manage to instill some material content. Roughly speaking, the structure of a domain is the system of relations that the elements of this same domain establish among themselves abstractly considered, i.e., re- gardless of what the elements or the relations among them are. Hence, the structure of any domain is an abstract aspect of this domain that can be reified (as an ideal object, or Form, to use Platonic jargon) which can be indifferently instantiated in any domain of a family of isomorphic domains (in Platonic language, all isomorphic domains participate in the same ideal Form). Although the structure of two different, but isomorphic domains are equal, they are not identical, for they are aspects of different domains. However, both are instances of the same ideal structure; we can say that the same identical ideal structure projects itself in equal, but non-identical structures of different isomorphic domains. Mathematics is solely concerned with structures, be they given as abstract aspects of determinate domains of objects (for example, the -structure of the domain of natural numbers) or ideal structures characterized by their properties (for example, the -struc- ture as given by second-order Dedekind-Peano axioms). Mathematical theories are al- ways structural descriptions, either in concreto, as contentual theories such as arithmetic 46 Jairo José da Silva seen as the description of the structure of the domain of natural numbers, or in abstracto, as formal theories, like formal second-order arithmetic. Let us consider an example. Let us postulate a domain (no matter which or even whether there really is such a domain; this postulation is a free act of imagination) whose elements (no matter what they are) are ordered (by no matter which binary relation) in a discrete linear order in such a way that there is a first element but not a last one, each element has another element – but only one – immediately following it and each element can be reached from the first in a finite number of steps (just like the natural numbers ordered by the successor relation). Regardless of the nature of the objects or the relation that orders them, the above description concerns only how the objects of the domain are ordered and is a typical example of a structural description in abstracto. An ideal structure is thus posited. Yet, in making this structural description, we may also have had a partic- ular, previously existing domain of entities under our eyes (or in the “mind’s eye”); for example, natural numbers ordered by successor relation, which would imply that the ac- count, in this case, would be one in concreto, describing the abstract structural aspect of a particular domain. Any contentual mathematical theory can, by formal abstraction, be made into a formal theory. If this is a categorical theory (all models are isomorphic), it is no longer a description in concreto of the abstract structure of a particular domain but a description in abstracto of an ideal structure. Non-categorical theories cannot completely character- ize a structure, since they are incomplete characterizations. But mathematics is often more interested in families of similar structures (for example, groups) than in single structures of the same family (for example, the group S ). A description (theory) is only capable of characterizing a family of similar structures, that of all the domains that correspond to this description (all the models of the theory). By keeping in mind that mathematics can only provide structural descriptions, we can see how it can be of help when we are precisely interested in the purely structural aspect of our experience of the world. Let us consider another example. Through our immediate experience, we may notice that bodies exposed to the sun feel warmer to the touch, some more than others. Our curiosity is stimulated, and we consequently put our- selves in a scientific state of mind. We are no longer content in describing our experience; we want to explain it, to bring out the “hidden rationality” of the phenomenon. Then, though maybe not always consciously, we formulate the “Galilean” hypothesis: there is a hidden legality connecting the period of time bodies are exposed to the sun and the Science and the Lebenswelt 47 increase of intensity in the feeling of warmth they cause when touched (and, if we are slightly more scientifically sophisticated, that this relation may depend on the type of body in question). We have isolated a particular structural aspect of empirical reality we happen to be interested in. To bring it out, so to speak, we resort to the “Galilean” strategy: we objectify the sensation of warmth, substituting it by the objective (scientific) notion of temperature, and different “degrees of warmth” actually or only potentially perceivable by numbers (this depends on how temperature relates to, for example, the length of a thin column of mercury). Now, based on the observable correlation between two series of numbers – one series measuring the body’s time of exposure to the sun, another the tem- perature change in this body due to exposure, idealizing and generalizing inductively – we may be able to arrive at a numerical formula, expressing an idealization of the corre- lation we want to bring to light. Now, all the questions we want to ask about our imme- diate experience (for example, how much warmer would a piece of iron feel after being exposed to the midday sun during my lunch break?) can be posed about its mathematical substitute (how much would the temperature of a piece of iron rise when exposed to the midday sun for an hour?). Once our formula is available, and the initial conditions checked, the answer is only a matter of arithmetical calculation. The mathematical sub- struction of experience is, in this particular case, complete. One aspect of the Galilean hypothesis in particular is worth noting, it is presup- posed that the mathematical “translation” is adequate, that is, that the mathematical rela- tion really does disclose something that was hidden in the world. In other words, if one presupposes that experienceable reality admits a hidden structure that is mathematically expressed. This, as Husserl emphasizes, is a hypothesis, and a very peculiar one. Our experience can neither confirm it nor can it disconfirm it. The hypothesis is out of reach for empirical testing. If the real world is, as Husserl wants, the experienceable world, then its real structure is the one we can experience. It can be mathematical in a certain sense; for instance, in our example, we can experience that short periods of exposure can cause only small changes in the feeling of warmth, i.e. that the continuum of periods of exposure is related to the continuum of increase in the warm feeling in a continuous man- ner. This is a topological property of experience, and as such mathematical. Its metrical Perception can also display quantitative aspects of experienceable reality (longer periods of exposure entail greater increase in the sensation of warmth) which, however, remain at the level of the morphological (as opposed to the exact). The formula gives these aspects an exact translation, which, although it does not 48 Jairo José da Silva translation, embodied in the formula that links temperature changes with periods of ex- posure (which expresses the intuitive properties of continuous correlations analytically), is an idealization that is not in principle capable of direct experience. The Galilean hy- pothesis consists in taking it as an adequate translation of the topological property, even though it involves more than what meets or can meet the senses. The philosophical error (which, however, is not a scientific error) lies in taking a hypothesis for a fact. Some aspects of experience can be mathematical, but not always in the same sense as their mathematical translations are. correspond to anything hidden in the real world, can be translated back in terms of elements of the experi- enceable world. Mathematics provides a representation, not a faithful picture; this is its methodological value. Science and the Lebenswelt 49 References Bloch, Felix (1976). “Heisenberg and the Early Days of Quantum Mechanics.” In Physics Today 29, no. 12: 23-27. Da Silva, Jairo José (2014). Husserl and the Principle of Bivalence. In: Hill, Clarice Ortiz; da Silva, Jairo José, 285-298. Da Silva, Jairo José (2017). “Husserl and Weyl” In Stefania Centrone (ed.) Essays on Husserl’s Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics. The Hague: Springer, pp. 317- Hill, Clarice Ortiz; da Silva, Jairo José (2013). The Road Not Taken, On Husserl’s Phi- losophy of Logic and Mathematics. London: College Publications. Hopkins, Burt. (2011). The Origins of the Logic of Symbolic Mathematics. London: Bloomington. Husserl, Edmund (2003). Philosophie der Arithmetik. Halle: Pfeffer, 1891; also published in Husserliana Bd. XII (The Hague 1970); English translation: Philosophy of Arithmetic, Psychological and Logical Investigations with Supplementary Texts from 1887-1901. Translated by D. Willard, Dordrecht. Husserl, Edmund (1970). Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzen- dentale Phänomenologie. Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie. In Husserliana. Bd. VI ed. W. Biemel, Husserliana (The Hague 1954); English translation: The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenol- ogy. Translated by David Carr Evanston. Ill. Klein, Jacob (1969). Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. Translated by Eva Brann. Cambridge, Mass : The MIT Press. Koyré, Alexander (1956). “Les origines de la science moderne.” Diogène 16: 14-42.
Phainomenon – de Gruyter
Published: Sep 1, 2022
Keywords: Mathematized science; Husserl; Lebenswelt; The crisis of science; The applicability of mathematics
You can share this free article with as many people as you like with the url below! We hope you enjoy this feature!
Read and print from thousands of top scholarly journals.
Already have an account? Log in
Bookmark this article. You can see your Bookmarks on your DeepDyve Library.
To save an article, log in first, or sign up for a DeepDyve account if you don’t already have one.
Copy and paste the desired citation format or use the link below to download a file formatted for EndNote
Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
All DeepDyve websites use cookies to improve your online experience. They were placed on your computer when you launched this website. You can change your cookie settings through your browser.